Top-Rated Free Essay
Preview

The study of logic

Good Essays
2914 Words
Grammar
Grammar
Plagiarism
Plagiarism
Writing
Writing
Score
Score
The study of logic
The study of Logic

Sound reasoning is the basis of winning at argument. Logical fallacies undermine arguments. They are a source of enduring fascination, and have been studied for at least two-and-a-half millennia. Knowledge of them is useful, both to avoid those used inadvertently by others and even to use a few with intent to deceive. The fascination and the usefulness which they impart, however, should not be allowed to conceal the pleasure which identifying them can give.

I take a very broad view of fallacies. Any trick of logic or language which allows a statement or a claim to be passed off as something it’s not has an admission card to the enclosure reserved for fallacies. Very often it is the case that what appears to be a supporting argument for a particular contention does notsupport it at all. Sometimes it might be a deduction drawn from evidence which does not sustain it.

Many of the fallacies are committed by people genuinely ignorant of logical reasoning, the nature of evidence, or what counts as relevant material. Others, however, might be committed by persons bent on deception. If there is insufficient force behind the argument and the evidence, fallacies can add enough weight to carry them through.

This book is intended as a practical guide for those who wish to win arguments. It also teaches how to perpetrate fallacies with mischief at heart and malice aforethought. I have described each X How to Win Every Argument fallacy, iven examples of it, and shown why it is fallacious. After any points of general interest concerning the history or occurrence of the fallacy, I have given the reader recommendations on how and where the fallacy may be used to deceive with maximum effect.

I have listed the fallacies alphabetically, although a full classification into the five major types of fallacy may be found at the end of the book. It is well worth the reader's trouble to learn the
Latin tags wherever possible. When an opponent is accused of perpetrating something with a Latin name it sounds as if he is suffering from a rare tropical disease. It has the added effect of making the accuser seem both erudite and authoritative.
In the hands of the wrong person this is more of a weapon than a book, and it was written with that wrong person in mind.
It will teach such a person how to argue effectively, even dishonestly at times. In learning how to argue, and in the process of practising and polishing each fallacy, the user will learn how to identify it and will build up an immunity to it. A working knowledge of these fallacies provides a vocabulary for talking about politicians and media commentators. Replacing the vague suspicion of double-dealing will be the identification of the precise crimes against logic which have been committed.
Knowledge of fallacies can thus provide a defensive as well as an offensive capability. Your ability to spot them coming will enable you to defend yourself against their use by others, and your own dexterity with them will enable you to be both successful and offensive, as you set about the all-important task of making arguments go your way.
Madsen Pirie

Abusive analogy
The fallacy of abusive analogy is a highly specialized version of the ad hominem argument. Instead of the arguer being insulted directly, an analogy is drawn which is calculated to bring him into scorn or disrepute. The opponent or his behaviour is compared with something which will elicit an unfavourable response toward him from the audience.
Smith has proposed we should go on a sailing holiday, though he knows as much about ships as an Armenian bandleader does.
(Perhaps you do not need to know all that much for a sailing holiday.
Smith can always learn. The point here is that the comparison is deliberately drawn to make him look ridiculous. There may even be several Armenian bandleaders who are highly competent seamen.)

The analogy may even be a valid one, from the point of view of the comparison being made. This makes it more effective, but no less fallacious, since the purpose is to introduce additional, unargued, material to influence a judgement.
If science admits no certainties, then a scientist has no more certain knowledge of the universe than does a Hottentot running through the bush. (This is true, but is intended as abuse so that the hearer will be more sympathetic to the possibility of certain knowledge.)
The fallacy is a subtle one because it relies on the associations which the audience make from the picture presented. Its perpetrator need not say anything which is untrue; he can rely on the associations made by the hearer to fill in the abuse. The abusive analogy is a fallacy because it relies on this extraneous material to influence the argument.

2 How to Win Every Argument
In congratulating my colleague on his new job, let me point out that has no more experience of it than a snivelling boy has on his first day school.
(Again, true. But look who's doing the snivelling.)
While politicians delight in both abuse and analogies, there are surprisingly few good uses of the abusive analogy from that domain. A good one should have an element of truth in its comparison, and invite abuse by its other associations. All other things being equal, it is easier to be offensive by making a comparison which is untrue, than to be clever by using elements of truth. Few have reached the memorable heights of Daniel
O'Connell's description of Sir Robert Peel:
...a smile like the silver plate on a coffin.
(True, it has a superficial sparkle, but it invites us to think of something rather cold behind it.)

The venom-loaded pens of literary and dramatic critics are much more promising springs from which abusive analogies can trickle forth.
He moved nervously about the stage, like a virgin awaiting the Sultan.
(And died after the first night.)
Abusive analogies take composition. If you go forth without preparation, you will find yourself drawing from a well-used stock of comparisons which no longer have the freshness to conjure up vivid images. Describing your opponents as being like
'straightlaced schoolmistresses' or 'sleazy strip-club owners' will not lift you above the common herd. A carefully composed piece of abusive comparison, on the other hand, can pour ridicule on
Accent 3 the best-presented case you could find: 'a speech like a Texas longhorn; a point here, a point there, but a whole lot of bull in between'. Accent
The fallacy of accent depends for its effectiveness on the fact that the meaning of statements can change, depending on the stress put on the words. The accenting of certain words or phrases can give a meaning quite different from that intended, and can add implications which are not part of the literal meaning:
Light your cigarette.
(Without accent it looks like a simple instruction or invitation.)
Light your cigarette.
(Rather than the tablecloth, or whatever else you feel in the mood to burn.) Light your cigarette.
(Instead of everyone else's.)
Light your cigarette.
(Instead of sticking it in your ear.)
Even with so simple a phrase, a changed accent can give a markedly changed meaning.
We read that men are born equal, but that is no reason for giving them all an equal vote.
4 How to Win Every Argument
(Actually, we probably read that men are born equal. Born equal carries an implication that they do not remain equal for long.)
Accent is obviously a verbal fallacy, for the most part.

Emphasis in print is usually given by italics, and those who supply them to a quotation from someone else are supposed to say so.
In speech, however, unauthorized accents intrude more readily, bringing unauthorized implications in their wake. The fallacy lies with the additional implications introduced by emphasis. They form no part of the statement accepted, and have been brought in surreptitiously without supporting argument.
The fallacy of accent is often used to make a prohibition more permissive. By stressing the thing to be excluded, it implies that other things are admissible.
Mother said we shouldn't throw stones or the windows.
It's all right for us to use these lumps of metal.
(And mother, who resolved never to lay a hand on them, might well respond with a kick.)
In many traditional stories the intrepid hero wins through to glory by using the fallacy of accent to find a loophole in some ancient curse or injunction. Perseus knew that anyone who looked at the Medusa would be turned to stone. Even villains use it: Samson was blinded by the king of the Philistines who had promised not to touch him.
Your most widespread use of the fallacy of accent can be to discredit opponents by quoting them with an emphasis they never intended. ('He said he would never lie to the American people. You will notice all of the things that left him free to do.')
Richelieu needed six lines by the most honest man in order to find something on which to hang him; with skilful use of the fallacy of accent you can usually get this down to half a line.
Accident 5
It is particularly useful when you are advocating a course of action which normally meets with general disapproval. Accent can enable you to plead that your proposed action is more admissible. ('I know we are pledged not to engage in germ warfare against people in far-away lands, but the Irish are not far away.') When trying to draw up rules and regulations, bear it in mind that there are skilled practitioners of the fallacy of accent quite prepared to drive a coach and six through your intentions. You will then end up with something as tightly worded as the old mail monopoly, which actually spelled out that people shouting across the street could be construed as a breach of the mail monopoly. (They did only say the street, though.)

Accident
The fallacy of accident supposes that the freak features of an exceptional case are enough to justify rejection of a general rule.
The features in question may be 'accidental', having no bearing on the matter under contention, and may easily be identified as an unusual and allowable exception.
We should reject the idea that it is just to repay what is owed. Supposing a man lends you weapons, and then goes insane? Surely it cannot be just to put weapons into the hands of a madman?
(This fallacy, used by Plato, lies in not recognizing that the insanity is an 'accident', in that it is a freak circumstance unrelated to the central topic, and readily admitted to be a special case.)
Almost every generalization could be objected to on the grounds that one could think of 'accidental' cases it did not cover. Most of the general statements about the consequences
6 How to Win Every Argument which follow upon certain actions could be overturned on the grounds that they did not cover the case of a meteorite striking the perpetrator before the consequences had occurred. To maintain this would be to commit the fallacy of accident.
It is a fallacy to treat a general statement as if it were an unqualified universal, admitting no exceptions. To do so is to invest it with a significance and a rigour which it was never intended to bear. Most of our generalizations carry an implicit qualification that they apply, all other things being equal. If other things are not equal, such as the presence of insanity or a meteorite, the exceptions can be allowed without overturning the general claim.
' You say you have never met this spy. Can you be sure he was never near you in a football crowd, for example?'
'Well, no.'
'When was this occasion, and what papers passed between you?1
(If I did meet him, it was an accident.)
Accident is a fallacy encountered by those in pursuit of universal.
If you are trying to establish watertight definitions of things like 'truth', justice' and 'meaning', you must not be surprised if others spend as much energy trying to leak the odd accident through your seals.
Plato was searching for justice. John Stuart Mill, trying to justify liberty except where there is harm, or serious risk of harm, to others, found himself forever meeting objections which began, 'But what about the case where . . . ? ' It is an occupational hazard. If you are to avoid accidents, avoid universal.
Promises should not always be kept. Suppose you were stranded on a desert island with an Austrian count who was running an international
Affirming the consequent 7 spy-ring. And suppose there was only enough food for one, and you promised him...
(The only amazing feature of these lurid stories is that anyone should suppose such freak cases to make the general rule any less acceptable.) One of the famous examples of the fallacy is a schoolboy joke:
What you bought yesterday you eat today. You bought raw meat yesterday, so you eat raw meat today.
(With the generalization referring to the substance, regardless of its
'accidental' condition.)
The fallacy of accident is a good one for anarchists because it appears to overturn general rules. When it is claimed that you are breaking the rules, dig up the freakiest case your imagination will allow. If the rule does not apply in this case, why should it apply in yours? ('We all agree that it would be right to burn down a tax office if this were the only way to release widows and orphans trapped in the cellar. So what I did was not inherently wrong...')
Affirming the consequent
To those who confuse hopelessly the order of horses and carts, affirming the consequent is a fallacy which comes naturally. An occupational hazard of those who engage in conditional arguments, this particular fallacy fails to recognize that there is more than one way of killing a cat.
When cats are bitten by rabid hedgehogs they die. Here is a dead cat, so obviously there is a rabid hedgehog about.
8 How to Win Every Argument
(Before locking up your cats, reflect that the deceased feline might have been electrocuted, garrotted, disembowelled, or run over. It is possible that a rabid hedgehog got him, but we cannot deduce it as a fact.) The arguer has mixed up the antecedents and consequents. In an 'if... then' construction, the 'if part is the antecedent, and the 'then' part is the consequent. It is all right to affirm the antecedent in order to prove the consequent, but not vice versa.
If I drop an egg, it breaks. I dropped the egg, so it broke.
(This is perfectly valid. It is an argument called the modus ponens which we probably use every day of our lives. Compare it with the following version.)
If I drop an egg, it breaks. This egg is broken, so I must have dropped it.
(This is the fallacy of affirming the consequent. There could be many other incidents leading to a broken egg, including something falling upon it, someone else dropping it, or a chicken coming out of it.)
For valid logic we must affirm the first part in order to deduce the second. In the fallacy we affirm the second part in an attempt to deduce the first. Affirming the consequent is fallacious because an event can be produced by different causes. Seeing the event, we cannot be certain that only one particular cause was involved.
If the Chinese wanted peace, they would favour cultural and sporting exchanges. Since they do support these exchanges, we know they want peace. (Maybe. This conclusion might be the most plausible, but there could be other, more ominous reasons for their support of international exchanges. The cat can be killed in more ways than one.)
This fallacy receives a plentiful airing in our law-courts, since it is the basis of circumstantial evidence. Where we have no
Amphiboly 9 eyewitness evidence, we work back from what is known to those actions which might have caused it.
If he had been planning murder, he would have taken out extra insurance on his wife. He did take out extra insurance.
If he intended poison, he would have bought some. He did buy some weedkiller. If he had wanted to cut up the body, he would have needed a big saw.
Such a saw was found in his toolshed.
(There could be alternative explanations, innocent ones, for all of these actions. It would be fallacious to say that any of them proved him guilty. But as they mount up, it becomes progressively easier for twelve good persons and true to eliminate reasonable doubts about coincidence. No doubt they are sometimes wrong and thereby has hanged many a tale, together with the occasional innocent man.)
This is an extremely good fallacy to use when you wish to impute base motives to someone. Motives do not show, but the actions caused by motives do. You can always gain a hearing for your suggestion of less-than-honourable motives, by use of a skilfully affirmed consequent.
She's just a tramp. Girls like that always flaunt themselves before men, and she did appear at the office party wearing a dress that was practically transparent! (We can all see through this one.)
Amphiboly
Amphiboly is the fallacy of ambiguous construction. It occurs whenever the whole meaning of a statement can be taken

You May Also Find These Documents Helpful

  • Good Essays

    In this paper I will be discussing two arguments models; one is from a philosopher‘s view and the other is from a psychologist’s view. I will explain how and why these models are important. I will also discuss my understanding of the thinking and justification of each model of argument by compare and contrasting the two arguments.…

    • 763 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Behind all fallacies there is major critical thinking. Not knowing how to think critical could jeopardize your argument in reasoning. Critical thinking, is analyzing further into a subject to get valid points in an argument. As we all know, fallacies are considered flawed ways into having invalid reasons. There are many reasons why fallacies are not very good to use in an argument. However, since there is a great quantity of fallacies. I will only discuss two fallacies, Faulty Analogy and Bandwagon.…

    • 477 Words
    • 2 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Logical Fallacies is done manipulatively, always done on purpose and targets people’s ignorance and more of stupidity. The trial of the slave known as tituba is a perfect example of logical fallacy, because she had got beat really bad.…

    • 314 Words
    • 2 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    • What are some examples of bias, fallacies, and specific rhetorical devices in the speech you selected?…

    • 739 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Better Essays

    sharp decline in the company's revenues. She asks her team to diagnose the issue and…

    • 1770 Words
    • 17 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Powerful Essays

    The first chapter introduced the reader to the art of rhetoric. He describes how rhetoric works through real life examples. He demonstrates ways that rhetoric persuades us like, argument from strength, and seduction. He tells the reader that the sole purpose of arguing is to persuade the audience. He showed that the chief purpose of arguing is to also achieve consensus, a shared faith in a choice.…

    • 2276 Words
    • 7 Pages
    Powerful Essays
  • Powerful Essays

    1. In order to argue effectively, the arguer must first set a personal goal, and then play an active role in setting the goals of the “audience”.…

    • 1800 Words
    • 8 Pages
    Powerful Essays
  • Good Essays

    A fallacy is a mistaken belief which is usually based on an unsound argument. One example of a fallacy is called an unsupported assertion. An unsupported assertion is an assertion which is not supported, but nevertheless constitutes a major part of an argument. In his argument against Romney, Gingrich, either unknowingly or purposefully, uses an unsupported assertion to paint Romney in an extremely negative light. Gingrich says, “I'm sure last night, at an elegant three-star restaurant in New York, that Mitt was fully at home, happy to share his vision of populism, which involved a little foie gras, a certain amount of superb cooking, but was…

    • 621 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Unit 3 Quiz

    • 518 Words
    • 3 Pages

     people are inherently able to figure out facts and figures for themselves, so fitting them into a logical framework doesn’t allow them to develop their own conclusions and relationships, which is the point of an argument…

    • 518 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Better Essays

    John Gatto Papaer

    • 1619 Words
    • 7 Pages

    Cited: Wood, Nancy, and Miller James. Perspectives On Argument. 7th ed. New Jersey: Pearson Education, 2012. Print…

    • 1619 Words
    • 7 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Good Essays

    2) An argument should be focused on winning over an audience rather than beating them…

    • 1230 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Logical Fallacies Handout

    • 501 Words
    • 2 Pages

    In an argumentative essay, the writer attempts to persuade the reader through the logic or rationality of her argument. If the writer’s essay is based on emotions or feelings, or if the rational thought is flawed (and therefore not rational), the argument loses its strength. Below is a list of logical errors commonly made by students in argumentative essays:…

    • 501 Words
    • 2 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Powerful Essays

    Course Syllabus

    • 3882 Words
    • 16 Pages

    University policies are subject to change. Be sure to read the policies at the beginning of each class. Policies may be slightly different depending on the modality in which you attend class. If you have recently changed modalities, read the policies governing your current class modality.…

    • 3882 Words
    • 16 Pages
    Powerful Essays
  • Good Essays

    Evidence is a valid reason to believe something because once something has been proven through observation, it cannot be argued. It is simply fact, according to Dawkins. On the other hand, when a claim is justified by tradition, authority or revelation there is still room for opinion and argument. When a fact can be argued, it is unfounded and therefore is not a fact at all. In the case of tradition, Dawkins explains that often traditions (specifically religions) stem from stories written long ago that were passed down through generations. Somewhere along the way, they began to be construed as fact, but there is no way of knowing for certain who originally believed them and whether they had evidence or even if they were meant to be taken seriously at all. He then rationalizes that the appeal to authority is fallacy because being in an authoritative position does not make a person all-knowing, nor does it mean that they are always right. Without evidence,…

    • 1107 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Better Essays

    Argument is an important activity in the advancement of knowledge and society. There are many ways to express your self in this world, art, music, writing, speaking, etc. Within those things are countless approaches to getting your point across, or defending your side of an argument. Some of these methods are more effective at showing others that your way is the right way.…

    • 1215 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Better Essays